Xen., Mem, 1.2.56. Again, his accuseralleged that he selected from the most famous poets the most immoral passages, and usedthem as evidence in teaching his companions to be tyrants and malefactors:

http://msuweb.montclair.edu/~furr/essays/ifstoneonsocrates.pdf| [email protected]| Retyped and HTML'ed 15 Feb 99; last modified30 September 2013

By I.F. Stone
Last year, on his 70th birthday, in an interviewwithhimself for this Magazine, retired journalist I.S. Stone spoke of hisnew-foundjoy in Greek studies and his hope of finding in them 'one last scoop'thatwould help clear up some of the mystery which still surrounds the trialof Socrates, that cause célèbre which has tantalizedscholarsand historians for centuries. Now, he believes he has found newevidencethat sheds light not only on the trial itself but on the complexpoliticsof fifth-century Athens. Here – again in a self-interview – Mr. Stonesetsforth his discovery and, at the same time, takes us on an adventure inlearning and an armchair tour of the ancient world.
Isn’t it a little late in the day to be re-examining thetrial ofSocrates? I thought that was 25 centuries ago?
It was held, to be exact, in 399 B.C.
And now, in A.D. 1979, you have discovered somethingnewsworthy –excuse the expression – about a trial that the wire services covered2378years ago?
This obsession with the trial of Socrates is not mine alone.Scholarsand historians have been puzzled by it for centuries, and still are.
What’s the puzzle?
The Athens of Socrates’s time has gone down in history as thevery placewhere democracy and freedom of speech were born. Yet that city putSocrates,its most famous philosopher, to death. Presumably this was because itcitizensdid not like what he was teaching. Yet he had been teaching there allhislife, unmolested. Why did they wait until he was 70, and had only a fewyears to live, before executing him?
Why should this fascinate an old Washington muckraker likeyou?
Because it’s a black eye for all I believe in, for democracyand freespeech. Anyone who starts out to study the problem of free speech indepth– as I did after ill health forced me to give up my Weekly – isirresistiblydrawn back to ancient Athens, where it all began.
Isn’t that pretty far from home base, from current concernsand difficulties?
Not really. All our basic problems are there in miniature. Ifell inlove with the Athenians and the participatory democracy they developed.Free discussion was the rule everywhere – in the Assembly, the lawcourts,the theatre, and the gymnasiums where they spent much of their leisure.Free speech – what the Greeks called parrhasia – was as muchtakenfor granted as breathing.
But then I was stopped, or stumped, by this contradictory andtraumaticspectacle of what they did to Socrates. These people and this city, towhich I look back for inspiration – how could they have condemned thisphilosopher to death? How could so blatant a violation of free speechoccurin a city that prided itself on freedom of inquiry and expression?
But why should we care at this late date?
Because Plato turned the trial of his master, Socrates, into atrialof Athens and of democracy. He used it to demonstrate that the commonpeoplewere too ignorant, benighted and fickle to entrust with politicalpower.In Plato’s 'Apology,' the contrast drawn between the nobility ofSocratesand the grim verdict of his juror-judges indicted democracy in the eyesof posterity. And thanks to his genius, no other trial except that ofJesushas so captured the imagination of Western man.
Plato made Socrates the secular martyred saint of the struggleagainstdemocracy. He stigmatized it as 'mobocracy.' Yet this was the very same'mob' which applauded the anti-war plays of Aristophanes when Athenswasfighting for its life against Sparta. (No such antiwar plays wereallowed,by either side, during our last two World Wars). This was the same'mob'whose eagerness for new ideas, and its readiness to hear them, drewphilosophersfrom all over the ancient world. It made Athens – in the proud words ofPericles – 'the school of Hellas,' the university of the Greek world.Itis the high repute of Athens that makes the trial of Socrates sopuzzling.
And now you think you can throw a little fresh light uponit?
I’ve been happily bogged down in ancient Athens for severalyears, tryingto explore all of Greek thought and civilization, in order to reach abetterunderstanding of the trial. In my researches amid the ancient documentsI recently stumbled on a crucial bit of evidence, hitherto overlooked,which makes the trial and its outcome a little less inexplicable.
I hope your life-insurance policies are fully paid up. Theclassicalscholars will be lying in wait for you, with knives sharpened. No trialin history has been more intimately studied, pored over and speculatedupon. And you, an interloper and – most horrid of academic epithets – a'journalist,' believe you have found something they all overlooked!Haveyou seen any unidentified flying objects lately.?
Sneer if you will, but I’ve been encouraged by a remark ofJakob Burckhardt,the great Swiss historian of the Renaissance and of Greek culture: Toemphasizethe importance of restudying the classics in every generation,Burckhardtonce said that, in a hundred years, someone would reread Thucydides andfind something in his history 'we had all overlooked.'
How can a newspaperman find something new to report about atrialthat took place so long ago?
You re-examine all the source material for yourself. You goback tothe texts in the original language, so that you can evaluate everynuance.You search out internal contradictions and curious evasions. It’s no sodifferent from digging the real truth out of a Pentagon or StateDepartmentdocument.
Could you fill me in on the sources for the trial – and doit, please,in less than three volumes?
I can do it in one sentence: The sources are scanty andone-sided. Theonly contemporary accounts are by two disciples of Socrates, Plato andXenophon, both anxious to put their beloved master in as good a lightaspossible. But they do not give us a transcript of the actual trial.Theygive us their own conception of what Socrates said, or perhaps theirownconception of what he should have said in his own defense. Plato’sexquisite,polished version, like his Socratic dialogues, can more reasonably bereadas fictionalized biography. In Xenophon, we are told that Socrates’s'innervoice' forbade him to prepare a defense. There is even one ancienttraditionthat tells us he was silent before his judges.
What of the prosecution’s side?
We have no record of it. We know it only by indirection fromthe two'Apologies,' one by Plato, the other by Xenophon – the word 'apology'inGreek means defense -- and from the 'memorabilia,' or memoirs, ofSocratesby Xenophon. It’s like trying to cover a trial when one is barred fromthe courtroom except to hear the defendant’s summation to the jury.
Do we know the actual charges against Socrates?
There were two charges: first, that Socrates violated the lawby 'refusingto do reverence to the gods recognized by the city, and introducingothernew divinities,' and second, by 'corrupting the youth.' But we do nothavethe text of the laws on which these charges were based, nor thespecificallegations.
So we do not know just what Socrates is supposed to have saidor donethat made him seem disrespectful of the city gods. Nor do we know whatwas meant by the charge of corrupting the youth. Under Athenian legalproceduresuch specifics were required in a preliminary complaint and hearingbeforea magistrate, who then decided whether the allegations and the evidencewere sufficient to warrant a trial. But we have no account of thispreliminaryprocedure, the equivalent of our grand jury.
Didn’t Plato’s dialogue the 'Euthyphro' cover thepreliminary examination?
That’s a common impression, but it’s wrong. The 'Euthyphro'picturesSocrates arriving for the preliminary hearing. But he gets no fartherthanthe portico of the examining magistrate. There he engages in a long andinconclusive conversation with Euthyphro, the defendant in anothercase.The subject they discuss is the proper definition of piety or holiness.It’s charming, but tells us nothing of what happened when Socrates wentin for his own arraignment.
Why do you think Plato chose to be so uninformative?
A lawyer might surmise that he blocked out as much as he couldof thespecific charges because they were too damaging and too hard todisprove.
Do you see the same defensive strategy in Plato’s 'Apology'?
I do. Socrates evades the charge that he did not respect thecity’sgods, and proves instead that he is not an atheist. But he was notchargedwith atheism. We never learn what was meant by corrupting the young.Thereader of Plato’s 'Apology' comes away with the impression thatthis wonderful old philosopher was condemned simply because he hadspenthis life exhorting his fellow citizens to be virtuous.
How do you account for his condemnation?
I believe the case against Socrates was political and that thechargeof corrupting the youth was based on a belief – and considerableevidence– that he was undermining their faith in Athenian democracy.
If so, why wasn’t the charge brought earlier? He had beenteachingfor a long time. A quarter century before the trial, Socrates hadalreadybeen attacked in Aristophanes’s play 'The Clouds' for running a 'thinkthank' whose smart-alecky graduates beat their fathers. If they thoughthim the source of such subversive teaching, why did the Athenians waituntil 399 B.C., when he was already an old man, before putting him ontrial?
Because in 411 B.C. and again in 404 B.C. antidemocrats hadstaged bloodyrevolutions and established short-lived dictatorships. The Athenianswereafraid this might happened again.
I haven’t found that in Plato.
Plato didn’t intend that you should. Those are the realitieshis 'Apology'was calculated to hide. Plato was a genius, a dazzling prestidigitator,with all the gifts of a poet, a dramatist and a philosopher. His'Apology'is a masterpiece of world literature, a model of courtroom pleading;andthe greatest single piece of Greek prose that has come down to us. Itrisesto a climax which never fails to touch one deeply, no matter how oftenit is reread. I read the 'Apology' in the original for the first timelastyear, slowly and painfully, line by line. When I came to the noblefarewellof Socrates to his judges, it gave me chest pains, it was so moving; Igladly offer up my angina in tribute to its mastery. 'I go to die,'Socratessays, 'and you to live, but which of us goes to the better lot is knownto none but God.’ Even Shakespeare never surpassed that! But these veryqualities also make Plato’s 'Apology' a masterpiece of evasion.
Is there any way to check Plato’s picture of the trialagainst theviews of the average Athenian?
We do have one piece of evidence which shows that even 50years afterthe event, when there had been ample time for reflection and remorsetheAthenians still regarded the trial as political, and the verdict asjustified.
Where did you find that?
In a speechby the famous orator Aeschines,the great rival of Demosthenes, in the year 345 B.C., just 54 yearsafterthe trial of Socrates. This bit is well known to scholars but itssignificancehas never been fully appreciated. With the clue Aeschines provides, wemay begin to reconstruct the Athenian political realities. Aeschinescitedthe case of Socrates as a praiseworthy precedent. 'Men of Athens,' hesaidto the jury court, 'you executed Socrates, the sophist, because he wasclearly responsible for the education of Critias, one of the thirtyanti-democraticleaders.'
Who was Critias?
He was the bloodiest dictator Athens had ever known, a pupilof Socratesat one time, and a cousin of Plato’s. Aeschines was saying in effectthatthe antidemocratic teachings of Socrates helped to make a dictator ofCritias,who terrorized Athens in 404 B.C. during the regime of the ThirtyTyrantsand just five years before the trial of Socrates. Critias seemed tohavebeen the most powerful member of the Thirty.
But why do you give so much weight to one sentence in oneman’s speechto an Athenian jury court 50 years after the trial?
Aeschines could not have swayed the jury by that referenceunless hewas saying something about the relations between Socrates and Critiaswhichwas generally accepted as true by the Athenian public opinion of thetime.Thought 50 years had passed, the dictatorship of Critias and the ThirtyTyrants must still have been a hateful memory. Justly or unjustly,Socrates’sreputation still suffered from his association with Critias. Thereferenceto Critias and Socrates proved effective demagogy. Aeschines won hiscase.
How do you account for the deep and enduring prejudiceagainst Socratesin his native city?
To understand this, one must touch on a damaging fact fewhistorianshave explained, or even mentioned, so great is the reverence forSocrates: Socrates remained in the city all through thedictatorship ofthe ThirtyTyrants.
Why do you put that in italics?
Because that single fact must have accounted more than anyother forthe prejudice against Socrates when the democracy was restored. ThethirtyTyrants ruled only about eight months, but it was a time of terror. Inthat period they executed 1,500 Athenians and banished 5,000, one-tenthor more of the total population of men, women, children and slaves.
When the Thirty Tyrants took power, they murdered or drove outof thecity all who were of the democratic party. A few months later, themoderateswho had originally supported the Thirty Tyrants began to flee,especiallyafter Critias murdered their leader, Theramenes. He, who had been oneofthe original Thirty Tyrants, was executed without a trial when he beganto criticize the Thirty Tyrants for their brutality.
Socrates was neither exiled with the democrats nor forced toflee withthe moderate oppositionists. He did not suffer at the hands of thethirtyTyrants unlike his chief accuser, Anytus, who lost much of his propertywhen he fled and joined the fight to free the city. Socrates, inPlato’s'Apology,' calls himself 'the gadfly' of Athens, but it seems his stingwas not much in evidence when Athens needed it most.
How does Plato handle this in the 'Apology'?
He never mentions Critias, or his past as a pupil of Socrates,nor doeshe dwell on the fact that Socrates stayed in the city all through thedictatorship.Instead Plato has Socrates represent himself as a man above the battleof politics.
How does Plato do that?
He has Socrates tell of two incidents in which he defiedunjust orders,once under the democracy, and again under the Thirty Tyrants. Under thedemocracy, he was presiding officer in the Assembly during the famoustrialof ten generals accused of misconduct for failing to succor survivorsandrecover the bodies of the slain after a naval victory. Socrates said heblocked the attempt to condemn them in one proceeding, because the lawcalled for a separate trial for each man. He added that he did so'althoughthe orators were ready to impeach and arrest me.'
Under the Thirty Tyrants, Socrates said, he had also resistedan unjustorder. Socrates and four others had been ordered to arrest a wealthyresidentalien whom the dictatorship wanted to kill so they could seize hisproperty.Such executions for revenue purposes were common under Critias.
Instead of obeying the order, Socrates says, 'I simply wenthome, andperhaps I should have been put to death for it, if the Government hadnotquickly been put down.' But he himself neither helped put it down, nortried to warn the victim, nor made a protest. Though he was alwayspreachingvirtue, he did not, like the Hebrew prophets, call such unvirtuousrulerspublicly to account.
But few modern readers know enough to resist Plato’s beguilingnarrative,and it serves to distract attention from the fact that nowhere in theancienttexts do we find Socrates resisting or deploring the overthrow of thedemocracy,nor welcoming its restoration. With the jury, this silence must haveoutweighedhis eloquence. The dictatorship of the thirty Tyrants was thedictatorshipof the wealthy landed aristocracy to which Plato and Critias belonged.This was the social circle from which most of Socrates’s followers weredrawn. Athens understood this, though the modern reader often doesn’t.
Does Xenophon – our other 'witness' on the trial – confrontthesecompromising political circumstances?
Xenophon does so in is 'Memorabilia' by quoting an unnamed'accuser.'This accuser has been variously identified as one of the accusers atthetrial or as a contemporary prodemocratic orator named Polycrates whose'pamphlet' on the trial of Socrates has since disappeared. In any case,Xenophon’s quotations from this accuser and his answer to theseaccusationsprovide us with some of the prosecution’s case against Socrates. In sodoing, Xenophon discloses much that Plato hides.
Where do you find the political issue in Xenophon?
In his 'memorabilia,' Xenophonreports that 'the accuser' said Socrates 'taught his pupils to lookdown upon the established laws’ by deriding the egalitarian method offillingmany minor offices in Athens by lot, and by teaching them thatgovernmentshould be left to experts instead of being determined by popular debateand vote in the assembly.
The 'accuser' said Socrates thus led the young 'to despise theestablishedconstitution and made them violent.' It is significant, but not oftennoticed,that Xenophon denies only the last part of this indictment. He couldhardlydeny the first two counts, since elsewhere in his memoirs of Socrateshefrequently quotes the old philosopher’s contempt for the assembly andforelection by lot. Xenophon passes over these accusations in silence. Buthe does deny that Socrates taught his pupils to use violence againstestablishedinstitutions. Xenophon insists he taught them it was wiser to proceedbypersuasion.
But Critias in power was hardly a model of persuasion.
Xenophon does not deny it. After all, our main source ofknowledge aboutthe misdeeds of Critias is Xenophon’s own history of his time, the'Hellenica.'Xenophon quotes the accuser as declaring that 'none wrought so manyevils'to the city of Athens as Critias and Alcibiades, the two most famouspupilsof Socrates. The accuser said that in the terrible days of the ThirtyTyrants,Critias 'bore the palm for greed and violence,’ while Alcibiades‘exceededall in licentiousness and insolence' under the democracy.
What defense did Xenophon offer?
'I have no intention,' Xenophonrepliesin the 'memorabilia,' of excusing the wrong these two men wroughtthestate.' But he claims they sought out Socrates as their teacher 'onlytoattain the utmost proficiency in speech and action.' And 'as soon astheythought themselves superior to their fellow disciples, they sprang awayfrom Socrates and took to politics.' With that answer most Socraticscholarshave been satisfied.
But you are not?
No. The question left open is what kind of politics Socratestaughtthem. Clearly from everything we learn elsewhere in Plato and Xenophon,it was an antidemocratic politics. Xenophon’s silence on the pointadmitswhat he cannot deny.
Does the 'accuser' in Xenophon link the Socratic teachingswith aristocraticattempts at tyranny, as in 411 and 404 B.C.?
Yes, but in a curious, indirect way. Healleged 'that Socrates, selecting the worst passages of the mostcelebratedpoets, and using them as arguments, taught those who kept him company[i.e.his pupils], to be unprincipled and tyrannical.'
Just what exactly did those terms mean?
A tyrant was someone who used violent and lawless methods toseize andmaintain power. The term 'unprincipled' is one translation of theadjectivalform of the Greek word kakourgos, which means, literally, anevil-doer.An Athenian would of course apply both terms to such men as Critias andthe Thirty Tyrants.
Does Xenophon deny that Socrates used quotations from thepoets thatmight encourage such behavior?
He doesn’t enter an explicit denial. Instead Xenophon, who isordinarilysuch a clear writer, gets fuzzy. This provoked my curiosity. In tryingto find out why, I stumbled on some fresh material. I found thatXenophonmade some striking omissions in discussing this accusation, and theomissionsobscured its significance.
What were the omissions?
First of all, in giving us examples from the poets to showwhat theaccuser meant, Xenophon limits himself to two poets. We know fromanothersource, the 'Apology' of Libanius, a fourth-century A.D. orator, thatthe'accuser' of Socrates cited four poets, not two, in this accusation.Thetwo Xenophon omits are Theognis and Pindar. Both were aristocraticpoets,notorious for their contempt, not only of the common people but of thenew middle class of merchants and traders who had begun to rival theoldlanded aristocracy. Pindar wrote his lovely odes to celebrate some oftheoutstanding tyrants of his time. By omitting Theognis and Pindar,Xenophonwas omitting the most obvious examples of what the accuser meant.
Who are the two poets Xenophon does quote?
Homer and Hesiod. But the quotations he gives seem to bearlittle, ifany relationship to the charge.
What do thequotations say?
The one from Hesiod says, 'Work is no disgrace, but idlenessis a disgrace.'Hesiod was a farmer poet, and this is from his 'Works and Days,' a kindof farmer’s almanac. That line is his expression of the work ethic. Iwillnot bore you with my fruitless efforts to find any sense in which thistrite but wholesome homily could possibly be interpreted as teachingtyrannicalconduct. Hesiod was no aristocrat but a hard-working Boetian peasantwhohated tyranny. I think the Hesiod quote has been screwed up for evasivepurposes.
What of the quotation from Homer?
Here we come to pay dirt. At first, the quotation from Homer,as givenby Xenophon in the 'memorabilia,' also seems to bear littlerelationshipto the accusation. It long puzzled me. I went to the commentators onthe'Memorabilia' without finding any enlightenment. Then I did what noneofthe commentators I read had done: I went back to Homer and took a lookat the context of the quotation. There I found Xenophon had made twoomissions,and suddenly I saw what the accuser was driving at. Here I believe Ihavefound fresh insight.
Is this a 'scoop' – if I may use so unscholarly a word?
I believe so. But to appreciate it, one must understand whatHomer meantto the Greeks. He was their Bible. And with them as with us, the devilcould quote Scripture to his purpose. A quotation from Homer waseffectiveas Holy Writ, and the two omissions Xenophon makes are of two passageswhich would have infuriated an Athenian democrat, but would havedelightedan anti-democratic aristocrat – because they would seem fully tojustifyviolent methods in putting down the democracy.
Can you tell us what was the Homeric episode referred to bythe 'accuser'in Xenophon?
It is in thesecond book of the 'Iliad.' The siege of Troy has been going on fornine years. The homesick and weary troops, just recently devastated bya plague, make a mutinous rush for the ships, determined to set sailforhome. Odysseus, the man of many wiles, intervenes to stem the panic.
How does Xenophon handle the episode?
He makes his quotations so minimal and selective as to blurthe pointof the accusation, and make it easier for Socrates to evade it.Xenophonquotes lines 188 to 191, and then skips to lines 198 to 202 from BookIIof the 'Iliad.'
In lines 188 to 191, Homer describes how Odysseus spoke 'withgentlewords' to the chieftains and aristocrats, while he tells us in lines198to 202 how differently he dealt with the common soldiers. When theangryhero encountered 'a man of the people,' Odysseus 'struck him with hisstaff,'calling him 'a worthless fellow' and ordering him to turn back from theships.
How would an Athenian react to this scene?
Very negatively. He was not used to being treated as aninferior eitherin peace or war. Xenophon’s account in the 'Anabasis' of how he led his10,000 mercenary Greek troops across Persia has been justly called apictureof 'a democracy on the march.'
Was anything important omitted in quoting these lines?
Yes. Xenophon omitted the last four lines of the speech madeby Odysseusas he struck and reviled the common soldiers. In those four omittedlinesOdysseus attacked the idea of democracy altogether. Homer in theselinessets forth for the first time in Western literature the doctrine of thedivine right of kinds. Here are the lines, in literal translation.Odysseustells the common soldiers:
We Achaeans can’t all be kings here
It is not good for the many to rule.
Let one man rule, one man be king,
To whom the son [Zeus] of wily Cronos
Has given the sceptre and the judgments
That he may take counsel for you.
That’s the doctrine of one man rule, and that’s just what Critias triedto impose on Athens. Xenophon could have denied that Socrates usedtheselines, or approved them. Instead Xenophon omitted them. The omission isa confession. These famous lines on kingship were too obviouslyanti-democraticteaching.
What was the third of the significant omissions to whichyou referred?
Xenophon omitted any mention of theassembly called by King Agamemnon to deal with the near mutiny.Assembliesare frequent in the 'Iliad.' This one turned out to be unique. It wastheonly assembly in all of Homer where a common soldier spoke up in thedebate.His name was Thersites, or The Brash One. To an Athenian, as to us, hethus represents the first stirrings of democracy in the Homericassemblies.
What happened to Thersites?
Odysseus beat the bold commoner until he bled, humiliated himin frontof the army and threatened to kill him if he ever spoke up again.
How does Homer treat this scene?
With approval. Homer sang his great lays in the halls of therich andpowerful, and clearly shows whose side he is on. Homer does not makeThersitesa hero, but a shrill and vulgar upstart. Few peoples have been assensitiveto beauty in form and in speech as the ancient Greeks. Homer paintsThersitesas bandy-legged, lame, hunchbacked and bald. One wonders how such acrippleever got into the army at all. The words Thersites uses are made asrepulsiveas his appearance. Homer calls them akosma. This is thenegativeof kosmos, whence our words 'cosmetics' and 'cosmos' derive.Theword implies disorder and lack of grace.
So what do you make of these omissions?
The accuser had charged that Socrates used certain passagesfrom Homerto teach his young aristocratic followers to be violent and tyrannical.In dealing with this mutinous episode, Xenophon omitted what theAtheniandemocrats would have regarded as the most subversive part of it: thefourlines on the divine right of kings, and Odysseus’s use of violence tosuppressfree speech in the assembly.
Homer was saying that the common people had no right to beheard. Therecould be no more sensitive point with the Athenian democrats. The rightto speak freely in the assembly was the foundation stone of Atheniandemocracy.Until the reforms of Solon, two centuries before the trial of Socrates,the common people of Athens could neither speak nor vote in theassembly.And again, just five years before the trial of Socrates, they had beenforcibly deprived of this precious right by the dictatorship ofCritias.In their eyes, this episode in Homer would seem to justify the violenttyranny they had so recently overthrown. I think that is why Xenophonomittedit from his defense of Socrates. They were too damaging a part of theprosecution’scase.
So you think Socrates was condemned because the Atheniansbelievedhis teachings had helped to produce such tyrants as Critias?
No, not exactly. The case is more complicated. Socrates wasprotectedfrom such a prosecution by the amnesty instituted by those whooverthrewand killed Critias. The dictatorship was crushed by a coalition of thedemocrats with moderate oligarchs who had been driven into oppositionbythe lawless extremism of the thirty. They took an oath to forget pastoffenses.The amnesty covered everybody but the remaining Thirty and theirleadingofficials. To prosecute Socrates as the teacher of Critias would havebeena violation of that solemn oath.
How do you know the oath was always honored?
All the surviving sources attest to it, and nowhere do Platoor Xenophoncharge, as they otherwise would, that the prosecution of Socrates was aviolation of the amnesty. The most striking testimonial to this is inAristotle’streatise on the Constitution of Athens where he says that theAthenians,after restoring their democracy, 'blotted out recriminations withregardto the past' and behaved both 'privately and publicly toward those pastdisasters' in ‘the most completely honorable and statesmanlike mannerofany people in history.' That was written a generation after the trialofSocrates.
So what conclusion do you draw?
When Xenophon discusses the charge that Socrates used certainpassagefrom Homer and other poets to teach his pupils to be lawbreakers andtyrannical,he had to be referring to teachings which continued after therestorationof the democracy. Athens felt that Socrates was still inculcatingdisrespectfor its democratic institutions, and feared an attempt to overthrow thedemocracy again.
Do you think this justified the condemnation of Socrates?
No. the 510-man jury itself was deeply troubled and reachedits verdictof guilty only by a narrow margin. But these fresh insights give us aglimpseof the political realities and extenuating circumstances which Plato,whohated democracy, did his best to hide – and which his 'Apology' has sosuccessfully obscured for 2,500 years.
Aeschines AgainstTimarchus173 (Loeb Classical Library)
Did you put to death Socrates the sophist,fellow citizens,because he was shown to have been the teacher of Critias, one of theThirtywho put down the democracy, and after that, shall Demosthenes succeedinsnatching companions of his own out of your hands, Demosthenes, whotakessuch vengeance on private citizens and friends of the people for theirfreedom of speech?
Xenophon Memorabilia1.2.9 (from PerseusProject)
But, said his accuser, he taught hiscompanions to despisethe established laws by insisting on the folly of appointing publicofficialsby lot, when none would choose a pilot or builder or flautist by lot,norany other craftsman for work in which mistakes are far less disastrousthan mistakes in statecraft. Such sayings, he argued, led the young todespise the established constitution and made them violent.
Xenophon, Mem.1.2.13.NowI have no intention of excusing the wrong these two men wrought thestate;but I will explain how they came to be with Socrates.
Xen., Mem,1.2.56. Again,his accuser alleged that he selected from the most famous poets themostimmoral passages, and used them as evidence in teaching his companionsto be tyrants and malefactors: